Ten serwis zostanie wyłączony 2025-02-11.
Nowa wersja platformy, zawierająca wyłącznie zasoby pełnotekstowe, jest już dostępna.
Przejdź na https://bibliotekanauki.pl

PL EN


Preferencje help
Widoczny [Schowaj] Abstrakt
Liczba wyników
Czasopismo
2015 | 4 | 2 | 16-25
Tytuł artykułu

Language as a Tool. An Insight From Cognitive Science

Warianty tytułu
Języki publikacji
EN
Abstrakty
EN
In this paper it has been argued that the theory of conceptual maps developed recently by Paul M. Churchland provides support for Wittgenstein’s claim that language is a tool for acting in the world. The role of language is to coordinate and shape the conceptual maps of the members of the given language community, reducing the cross-individual cognitive idiosyncrasies and paving the way for joint cognitive enterprises. Moreover, Churchland’s theory also explains our tendency to speak of language as consisting of concepts which correspond to things we encounter in the world. The puzzle of common sense reference is no longer a puzzle: while at the fundamental level language remains a tool for orchestrating conceptual maps, the fact that the maps encode some communally shared categorization of experience fuels our talk of concepts capturing the essences of things, natural kinds, prototypes, etc.
Wydawca
Czasopismo
Rocznik
Tom
4
Numer
2
Strony
16-25
Opis fizyczny
Daty
wydano
2015-06-01
online
2015-07-24
Twórcy
  • Jagiellonian University; Copernicus Center for Interdisciplinary Studies, Krakow, Poland, bbroze@yahoo.com
  • Pontifical University of John Paul II; Copernicus Center for Interdisciplinary Studies, Krakow, Poland, mateuszhohol@gmail.com
Bibliografia
  • 1. Brożek, B. Rule-Following. From Imitation to the Normative Mind, Kraków: Copernicus Center Press, 2013.
  • 2. Brożek, B., Hohol, M. Umysł matematyczny, Kraków: Copernicus Center Press, 2014
  • 3. Brożek, B., Olszewski, A. “The Mathematics of the Transcendental Ego”, Copernicus Center Reports 2, 2011, 75-124.
  • 4. Churchland, P.M. Plato’s Camera How the Physical Brain Captures a Landscape of Abstract Universals, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press 2012.
  • 5. Descartes, R. The Principles of Philosophy, translated by J. Veitch, , 1901.
  • 6. Gärdenfors, P. Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2000.
  • 7. Gärdenfors, P. The Geometry of Meaning: Semantics Based on Conceptual Spaces, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2014.
  • 8. Fodor, J. The Language of Thought, Crowell Press: New York, 1975.
  • 9. Hamming, R. “The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics”, The American Mathematical Monthly, 87(2), 1980, p. 81-90.
  • 10. Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason, translated by P. Guyer and A.W. Wood, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge 1998.
  • 11. Locke, L. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Hazleton: Pennsylvania University Press, 2009
  • 12. Margolis, E., Laurence, S. “Concepts”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <>.
  • 13. Müller, M. “On Thought and Language”, Monist 1(4), 1891, p. 572-589.
  • 14. Pais, A. Niels Bohr’s Times in Physics, Philosophy, and Polity, Oxford – New York: Oxford University Press, 1991.
  • 15. Tomasello, M. The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001.
  • 16. Vygotsky, L. Thought and Language, Cambridge, MA: Harvard Unviersity Press, 1986.
  • 17. Winger, W. “The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences”, Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics 13(1), 1960, p. 1-14.
  • 18. Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986.
Typ dokumentu
Bibliografia
Identyfikatory
Identyfikator YADDA
bwmeta1.element.doi-10_1515_sh-2015-0013
JavaScript jest wyłączony w Twojej przeglądarce internetowej. Włącz go, a następnie odśwież stronę, aby móc w pełni z niej korzystać.